Source
Chapter 1: Basics of human society
1) Why man may not live in solitude.
An individual is
bound to serve others in a variety of ways with his property, his
labor, his help, and his example. Because he cannot fully meet
these obligations as long as he lives alone in solitude, indeed
cannot even perfect his own situation in isolation as well as when
he lives among others, for he is obligated to make the best of his
situation to the fullest extent possible, and so he is not to live
in isolation from other humans like animals, but rather humans are
bound to live together and with each other, so that one can
promote the other's happiness, to the extent that each can.
Animals can live in isolation from the others because they do not
need much and in particular because they cannot learn much from
each other to improve their situation. Their body is composed of
their limbs in such a way that the nature of those circumstances
in which they find themselves determines their useful
movements.
2) What society is.
When people come together as one to
unify forces to promote thereby their common good, they give
themselves over to a society together. And accordingly that
society is nothing other than a contract of individuals with
unified forces whereby they promote their common good.
3) The composition of the common welfare.
The unimpeded
progress towards promotion of the common good which one hopes to
achieve through unified forces is called the welfare of society.
There is a good reason for this movement. For we cannot view the
welfare of a society as anything other than the greatest good that
a society of that nature can achieve. For this consists of
unimpeded progress towards greater perfection. Thus we cannot seek
the welfare of a society in anything other than unimpeded progress
for the promotion of the common good.
4) Aims of society and how they are distinguished.
Because
we strive to preserve this welfare through society, it is the aim
of society, and society is a means to advance the common welfare.
Because every society has a common welfare, and cannot exist
without one, every society has its own particular aim, which
distinguishes it from others. And societies must distinguish these
patterns within their aims, and then make decisions with which one
can achieve these.
5) Which societies are right and not right.
Because every
society is a contract, but no contract is valid as long as the two
parties, or even one of them, make such promises as run counter to
the laws of nature, no society can be right which has as its aim
anything which runs counter to the laws of nature, or in which one
or both parties promises anything which runs counter to them. On
the other hand, all societies are in accordance with the laws of
nature when neither side is promised more than is in accordance
with these laws.
6) A society constitutes a single person, and what follows from
this.
Because in a society two or more people become united
to combine their forces and advance their common good, they are in
this instance not to be viewed differently than as one individual,
and accordingly have a joint interest: and thus it is contrary to
the nature of a society that one seeks to pit the interest of one
against the interest of the other, or (what amounts to the same),
the welfare of one against the welfare of the other. And it thus
becomes clearer that it is not right if one member of a society
seeks his own welfare without regard for, or even at the expense
of, the welfare of another.
7) When one may not remain in a society.
Just as one is
not obligated to uphold a contract that runs counter to the laws
of nature, no one is required to remain in a society which is
unjust. And just as one is not obligated to uphold a contract into
which one was intimidated or tricked, one is not required to
remain in a society into which one was drawn by fear or
deception.
8) It is expanded further.
Again, because a society is
formed in the interest of the common good, but this is not upheld
if one or more parties seek their own advantage at the expense of
the others, the party which is thereby injured is not obligated to
remain in the society should he be able to separate himself from
it without incurring even greater losses. For if the circumstances
are such that he cannot exit the society without incurring even
greater losses to himself, then he is admittedly obligated to
endure the lesser injury and remain in the society.
9) Instances in which one is not allowed to renounce the
society.
Because no one is allowed to damage the other, we
cannot remove ourselves from or renounce a society—in other words,
we are not free to declare that we do not want to remain in it—so
long as the other will thereby incur injury. And if we do so
despite this, we are obligated to compensate him for the losses.
And the opposite is clear, that we can renounce it, if this does
no harm to the other, and even more so if we would incur losses if
we should remain part of it, but the other party would not profit
from our losses.
10) What is not to be tolerated in society.
Because all
those who live alongside and with each other in society should
employ all their forces in order to achieve that aim to which end
they formed the society, it cannot be permitted that one or the
other take any actions that are counter to this aim. If, however,
this should happen, the losses caused must be repaid by the guilty
party, and the others have the right to employ all means necessary
to cause him to fulfill this obligation.
11) Central laws of society.
Namely, that the welfare of
the society is the primary end to which one commits to it, all
other aims are to be arranged such that they are in the end a
means to this primary aim. So this is the rule that the parties
that live together in a society should follow in their actions, to
the extent that they live together like this: Do whatever advances
the welfare of the society and desist from anything which hinders
or damages it. And because we are obligated to conduct ourselves
according to this rule, this is the ultimate law of a society, and
one does not say without cause that the common good is the highest
or final law in a society.
12) When the common welfare of a particular party is to be
granted preference.
Thus, if it should happen that the
particular welfare of a single party who lives within the society
is not compatible with the common welfare and it should thus be
necessary to make an exception, then the common welfare must be
given priority over the particular, and the particular thus placed
after the common welfare. One must be careful, however, that one
does not take the common welfare further than the aim of the
society demands.
13) When strangers are to be considered after those within the
society.
Again, because the various people who live together
in a society are to be viewed as a single person in respect of
their common welfare, but we are not obligated to help others
within it, if we would thereby have to neglect our own [needs], no
one is obligated to help others if this would disadvantage the
welfare of those who live in society with us. For this reason, our
own are to be given priority over those who do not live together
with us in society.
14) How far a society can place obligations on
others.
Similarly, because the various individuals who live
together in one society are to be viewed in regard to their common
welfare as a single person, other societies are also to be viewed
as other people. And according to this, what one person owes
another, one society likewise owes the other. Thus a society is
not obligated to help another to achieve that which it could do on
its own, but is [obligated to provide that help] which it cannot
do on its own, but we have the power to do.
15) Differences within societies.
Those who live next to
each other in a society are called members. And when those members
are individual people, one calls it a simple society: but if the
members are simple or less composite societies, a composite
society. Because one can view the simple societies as individual
persons, one can also view the composite as simple.
Source: Christian von Wolff, Vernünfftige Gedancken von dem gesellschafftlichen Leben der Menschen und insonderheit dem gemeinen Wesen. Zu Beförderung der Glückseeligkeit des menschlichen Geschlechtes. Den Liebhabern der Wahrheit mitgetheilet von Christian Wolffen. Halle: Renger, 1721, p. 1–9. Available online: https://www.deutschestextarchiv.de/wolff_gesellschaftlichesleben_1721.